Essays & Insigths
Received: 26 November 2019
Accepted: 17 March 2020
DOI: 10.30800/mises.2020.v8.1258
Abstract: Economics in One Lesson is the best introduction to economics ever written. It has enticed, educated, and inspired multitudes of people to embrace the teachings of the dismal science. To the extent that if there is any understanding of economics by the general public, it is due more to this book than to any other. Yet, I have uncovered one error in it, which I attempt to rectify, offering a very slightly improvement to a priceless book on economics.
Keywords: Elasticity, Parity Prices, Costs, Profit.
Resumen: La economía en una lección es la mejor introducción a la economía que alguna vez se ha redactado. Ha atraído, educado e inspirado a multitudes de personas a abrazar las enseñanzas de la ciencia sombría. En la medida en que haya una comprensión de la economía por parte del público en general, esto se debe más a este libro que a cualquier otro. Sin embargo, he descubierto un error en él, cuya rectificación es mi intento de mejorar muy levemente un libro invaluable sobre economía.
Palabras clave: Elasticidad, precios de paridad, costos, ganancias.
Resumo: Economia em uma única lição é a melhor introdução à economia que já foi escrita. Atraiu, educou e inspirou milhares de pessoas a adotar os ensinamentos da ciência sombria. Na medida em que existe uma compreensão da economia por parte do público em geral, isso se deve mais a esse livro do que a qualquer outro. No entanto, descobri um erro nele, cuja retificação é minha tentativa de melhorar, levemente, um livro inestimável sobre economia
Palavras-chave: Elasticidade, paridade de preços, custos, lucros.
Introduction1
I owe my career in economics to Hazlitt (1946).2 I use this book in my introduction to microeconomics classes, and I am very grateful to its author for writing it. Economics in One Lesson is, in my opinion, the very best introduction to economics, bar none, ever written.
Why, then, besmirch this magnificent publication with criticism? There are several justifications for such an unseemly initiative. First, “you can’t have too much of the truth.” Truth is its own reward. Truth is the byword of our profession, and, indeed, of every profession worthy of its name. If we do not attempt to wield the “terrible swift sword” of truth wherever it leads us, without fear or favor, we are not worthy of the honorific, “economists.” Second, from a pragmatic point of view, better that I, a strong supporter of this book3 call into question one erroneous point made by Hazlitt, in order to very slightly improve the book, than to have a critic of this author’s philosophy do so, in an attempt to discredit it. Thus, a benefit of the present criticism is that it might obviate one made with very different motives than those of its author.
First, the background (1946, p. 91):
The argument for parity prices ran roughly like this. Agriculture is the most basic and important of all industries. It must be preserved at all costs. Moreover, the prosperity of everybody else depends upon the prosperity of the farmer. If he does not have the purchasing power to buy the products of industry, industry languishes. This was the cause of the 1929 collapse, or at least of our failure to recover from it. For the prices of farm products dropped violently, while the prices of industrial products dropped very little. The result was that the farmer could not buy industrial products; the city workers were laid off and could not buy farm products, and the depression spread in ever-widening vicious circles. There was only one cure, and it was simple. Bring back the prices of the farmer’s products to a parity with the prices of the things the farmer buys. This parity existed in the period from 1909 to 1914, when farmers were prosperous. That price relationship must be restored and preserved perpetually.
What, then, is the problematic passage? It occurs as a part of (HAZLITT, 2008, p. 95) rejection of “parity prices”: “… when the farmer reduces the production of wheat to get parity, he may indeed get a higher price for each bushel, but he produces and sells fewer bushels. The result is that his income does not go up in proportion to his prices”.
When price rises and quantity falls, what happens to total revenue? It all depends upon the elasticity of the demand curve between those two points; e.g., the lower the price and the higher the quantity with which we begin, the higher price and lower quantity at which point we end. If the demand curve is inelastic, the farmers’ total revenue rises; if unitary, then it remains the same; and if elastic, then it falls, as we move up and to the left along the demand curve4.
Suppose the former. We posit, then, that the demand curve is inelastic5 at its relevant section. That means the revenue accruing to the farmers rises. Does that logically imply that “his income does not go up in proportion to his prices?” Not necessarily. Hazlitt does not take cognizance of the fact that, when quantity falls, so do costs. This is true, to be sure, not if he burns his crops. Then, costs do not fall; they even rise, since setting them on fire is not a costless activity. However, if he does not plant these crops in the first place, he saves on land rent,6 fertilizer, seeds, and power for his tractor etc. Thus, his costs decrease. Then, given the cost concatenations, it is possible that the farm income “go up in more than proportion to his prices”, contrary to Hazlitt’s statement
Let us consider some numerical examples. We will illustrate this point in three ways. First, with a demand curve that is elastic within the bounds we are considering; second, with one that is inelastic; and; third, with one of unitary elasticity.
1. Elastic case
Suppose price rises from 10 to 11, an increase of 10%, while quantity falls from 100 to 90. Total revenue falls from $1000 to $990, and the elasticity between these two points on the demand curve is 21/19, or elastic. In order to have a rise of more than 10% in income, we must go not from $1000 to $990, but from $1000 to $1100 or more. This would require a cost saving from the decrease in production of anything more than $110. Posit that the cost saving is $120, when quantity decreases from 100 to 90. Then, revenue will increase from $1000 to $1110, a rise of more than 10%. For costs to decrease by $120 when quantity decreases by 10 units (from 100 units to 90 units) the average cost per unit must decrease by $10; i.e., $12/unit. However, if the original price was $10 per unit, the original cost must have been no more than $10/unit, assuming a viable enterprise. So, even if the firm were operating at breakeven originally and it raised its price to $11/unit, cost must have dropped from $10/unit to -$2/unit for this scenario to work.
Is this logically possible? Yes. Anything that does not constitute a logical contradiction is possible, and this scenario does not constitute a logical contradiction. Is it plausible? Certainly not, under the assumption of a “viable enterprise.” But not all enterprises are viable. In the real world, which we presume is the one which Hazlitt addresses, there are always some firms making a profit, others breaking even, and others yet undergoing losses. Since we are now discussing agriculture, the latter is more likely than in other industries.7 It is beyond the scope of the present paper to speculate on any such statistics; all we can say for sure is that for some farmers, this numerical example is likely. Hazlitt warns against (1946, p. 15-16, [emphasis added by the author]) “… the persistent tendency of men to see only the immediate effects of a given policy, or its effects only on a special group, and to neglect to inquire what the long-run effects8 of that policy will be not only on that special group, but on all groups. Farmers who are losing money are a “special group” that we choose not to ignore.
2. Inelastic case9
Suppose price rises from 10 to 20, an increase of 100%, while quantity falls from 100 to 90. Total revenue increases from $1000 to $1800, and the elasticity between these two points on the demand curve is 3/19, or inelastic. In order to have a rise of more than 100% in income, or a doubling, we must go not from $1000 to $1800, but from $1000 to $2000 or more. This would require a cost saving from the decrease in production of anything more than $200. Posit that the cost saving is $300, when quantity decreases from 100 to 90. Then, revenue will more than double from $1000 to $2100, a rise of more than 100%. In this case MR = +800/-10 = -80 (per unit). Profit maximization (in this case, loss minimization) would require MC = -$80/unit. This implies a cost saving of $20/unit when price starts at $10/unit. Again, if we are analyzing the situation of profit earning farmers, or of those breaking even, this scenario must be rejected. However, as Shakespeare informs us: “There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are dreamt of in your philosophy.” In our philosophy, there are also tillers of the soil who undergo losses.
3. Unitary elasticity10
Suppose price rises from 10 to 11, an increase of 10%, while quantity falls from 11 to 10. Total revenue remains at $110, and the elasticity between these two points on the demand curve is 1, or elastic. In order to have a rise of more than 10% in income, we must go not from $110 to $120, but from $110 to $121 or more. This would require a cost saving from the decrease in production of anything more than $11. Posit that the cost saving is $12, when quantity decreases from 11 to 10. Then, revenue will rise from $110 to $122, an increase of more than 10%. To be sure, a cost a saving of $12 for a one unit decrease in sales with an original price of $10/unit means operating at a loss, and then having negative marginal cost. As we have seen, however, there is nothing implausible, let alone impossible, about such situation.
This error is no big deal. It is almost, but not quite, comparable to a typographical error. One would imagine that were Hazlitt to read this note, he would quickly acquiesce in the notion that if the cost savings of producing were sufficient, then, yes, the farmers’ income could indeed rise more than in proportion to the price increase.
Nor is this error based on fallacious considerations such as the Giffen Good11. Here, there is nothing as untoward. It is just a simple failure to note that with a lower quantity, it is entirely possible that the costs of production will fall, and by an amount large enough so as to render Hazlitt’s conclusion untrue.
References
ANDERSON, William et al. The Microsoft Corporation in Collision with Antitrust Law. The Journal of Social, Political and Economic Studies, v. 26, n. 1, p. 287-302, 2001.
AP. 1988. Farm Population Lowest Since 1850’s. Available at: https://www.nytimes.com/1988/07/20/us/farm-population-lowest-since-1850-s.html. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
ARMENTANO, Dominick T. The Myths of Antitrust. New Rochelle: Arlington House, 1972.
ARMENTANO, Dominick T. Antitrust and Monopoly: Anatomy of a Policy Failure. New York: Wiley, 1982.
ARMENTANO, Dominick T. Antitrust Reform: Predatory Practices and the Competitive Process. Review of Austrian Economics, v. 3, p. 61-74, 1989. Available at: http://www.mises.org/journals/rae/pdf/rae3_1_4.pdf. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
ARMENTANO, Dominick T. Antitrust: The Case for Repeal. Auburn: Mises Institute, 1999.
ARMSTRONG, Don. Competition vs. Monopoly. Vancouver: The Fraser Institute, 1982.
BARNETT, William II; BLOCK, Walter E. Mises never used demand curves: was he wrong? Ignorant? No: The Antimathematicality of Demand Curves. Dialogue, v. 1, p. 23-31, 2010. Available at: http://www.uni-svishtov.bg/dialog/title.asp?lang=en&title=101. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
BARNETT, William; BLOCK, Walter E.; SALIBA, Michael. Perfect Competition: A Case of Market-Failure. Corporate Ownership & Control, v. 2, n. 4, p. 70-75, 2005.
BARNETT, William II; BLOCK, Walter E.; SALIBA, Michael. Predatory pricing. Corporate Ownership & Control, v. 4, n. 4, p. 401-406, 2007.
BLOCK, Walter E. Thymology, praxeology, demand curves, Giffen goods and diminishing marginal utility. Studia Humana, v. 1/2, p. 3-11, 2012. Available at: http://studiahumana.com/pliki/wydania/Thymology,%20praxeology,%20demand%20curves,%20Giffen%20goods%20and%20diminishing%20marginal%20utility.pdf;wageshttp://studiahumana.com/art,The-second-issue,Thymology-Praxeology-Demand-Curves-Giffen-Goods-and-Diminishi.html. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
BLOCK, Walter E.; BARNETT, William II. Giffen Goods, Backward Bending Supply Curves, Price Controls and Praxeology. Revista Procesos de Mercado, v. 9, n. 1, p. 353-373, 2012.
BLOCK, Walter E.; PHILBOIS, Gabriel. Giffen Goods and Backward Bending Supply Curves of Labor. Revista Estudios Libertarios, v. 1, p. 55-69, 2018. Available at: http://www.notaslibertarias.com/vol-1-2018/. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
BLOCK, Walter E. Austrian Monopoly Theory - a Critique. The Journal of Libertarian Studies, v. 1, n. 4, p. 271-279, 1977.
BLOCK, Walter E. Amending the Combines Investigation Act. Vancouver: The Fraser Institute , 1982.
BLOCK, Walter E. Total Repeal of Anti-trust Legislation: A Critique of Bork, Brozen and Posner. Review of Austrian Economics, v. 8, n. 1, p. 35-70, 1994.
BLOCK, Walter; BARNETT, William. Monopsony Theory. American Review of Political Economy, v. 7, n. 1/2, p. 67-109, 2009. Available at: http://www.arpejournal.com/ARPEvolume7number1-2/Block-Barnett.pdf. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
BLOCK, Walter E.; WYSICKI, Igor. A defense of Rothbard on the demand curve against Hudik’s critique. Acta Economica et Turistica, p. 47-61, 2018. Available at: https://hrcak.srce.hr/index.php?show=clanak&id_clanak_jezik=296319. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
BOUDREAUX, Donald J.; DILORENZO, Thomas J. The Protectionist Roots of Antitrust. Review of Austrian Economics, v. 6, n. 2, p. 81-96, 1992.
COSTEA, Diana. A Critique of Mises’s Theory of Monopoly Prices. The Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, v. 6, n. 3, p. 47-62, 2003. Available at: http://www.mises.org/journals/qjae/pdf/qjae6_3_3.pdf. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
DILORENZO, Thomas J. The origins of antitrust: an interest-group perspective. International Review of Law and Economics, v. 5, p. 73-99, 1985. Available at: http://mason.gmu.edu/~trustici/LAW108/The%20Origins%20of%20Antitrust-%20An%20Interest%20Group%20Perspective.pdf. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
DILORENZO, Thomas J. The Myth of Natural Monopoly. Review of Austrian Economics, v. 9, n. 2, p. 43-58, 1996. Available at: http://www.mises.org/journals/rae/pdf/rae9_2_3.pdf. Acessed at: Jul 1 2019.
DILORENZO, Thomas J. The Truth About Sherman. Available at: Available at: https://mises.org/library/truth-about-sherman. Acessed: Nov 8 2019.
DILORENZO, Thomas J.; HIGH, Jack. Antitrust and Competition, Historically Considered. Economic Inquiry, v. 26, n. 1, p. 423-435, 1988.
HAZLITT, Henry. Economics in One Lesson. Auburn: Mises Institute , 2008 [1946].
HENDERSON, David R. The Robber Barons: Neither Robbers nor Barons. Library of Economics and Liberty, 2013. Available at: http://www.econlib.org/cgi-bin/printarticle2.pl?file=Columns/y2013/Hendersonbarons.html. Acessed: Mar 24 2019.
HIGH, Jack. Bork’s Paradox: Static vs Dynamic Efficiency in Antitrust Analysis. Contemporary Policy Issues, v. 3, p. 21-34, 1985.
HULL, Gary. The Abolition of Antitrust. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 2005.
KLEIN, Peter G. A note on Giffen goods. Unpublished, n/d. Available at: http://web.missouri.edu/~kleinp/misc/giffen.pdf. Acessed: 1 Jul 2019.
KLEIN, Peter G.; SALERNO, Joseph T. Giffen’s Paradox and the Law of Demand. Unpublished, n/d. Available at: https://mises.org/library/giffen%E2%80%99s-paradox-and-law-demand. Acessed: 1 Jan 2020.
MCCHESNEY, Fred. Antitrust and Regulation: Chicago’s Contradictory Views. Cato Journal, v. 10, 1991.
MCGEE, John S. Predatory Price Cutting: The Standard Oil (New Jersey) Case. The Journal of Law and Economics, p. 137-169, 1958.
MURPHY, Robert P.; WUTSCHER, Robert; BLOCK, Walter E. Mathematics in Economics: An Austrian Methodological Critique. Philosophical Investigations, v. 33, n. 1, p. 44-66, 2010. Available at: http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1467-9205.2009.01397.x/full. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
PHILBOIS, Gabriel; BLOCK, Walter E. The Z Curve: Supply and Demand for Giffen Goods. MISES: Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, Law and Economics, v. 6, n. 3, 2018. Available at: https://misesjournal.org.br/misesjournal/article/view/311. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
ROTHBARD, Murray N. Man, Economy and State. Auburn: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2004 [1962].
SHUGART, William F. Don’t Revise the Clayton Act, Scrap It!. Cato Journal, v. 6, 1987.
SMITH, Jr.; FRED, L. Why not Abolish Antitrust?, Regulation 1983. Available at: http://cei.org/op-eds-and-articles/why-not-abolish-antitrust. Acessed: Jan 23 2020.
TUCKER, Jeffrey. Controversy: Are Antitrust Laws Immoral?. Journal of Markets & Morality, v. 1, n. 1, 1998a. Available at: http://www.acton.org/publications/mandm/mandm_controversy_35.php. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
TUCKER, Jeffrey. Controversy: Are Antitrust Laws Immoral? A Response to Kenneth G. Elzinga. Journal of Markets & Morality, v. 1, n. 1, p. 90-94, 1998b. Available at: http://www.acton.org/publications/mandm/mandm_controversy_37.php. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
U.S. Census Bureau 2014. Available at: https://www.census.gov/prod/www/agriculture.html. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
U.S. Census Bureau 2019. Available at: https://www.nass.usda.gov/AgCensus/. Acessed: Jan 1 2020.
WYSOCKI, Igor; BLOCK, Walter E. The Giffen good - a praxeological approach. Ekonomia Wrocław Economic Review, v. 24, n. 2, p. 9-22, 2018. Available at: http://repozytorium.uni.wroc.pl/dlibra/publication/100651/edition/94179/content?ref=desc. Acessed: Jul 1 2019.
Notes
Author notes
Email: wblock@loyno.edu